The practice of argument-reconstruction - summary of chapter 5 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Critical thinking
Chapter 5

The practice of argument-reconstruction


Extraneous material

The first step in reconstructing an argument is to make a list of the argument’s premises and conclusion as concisely and clearly as possible.
Making such a list is only the first step towards a complete reconstruction.

Defusing the rhetoric

Expressive epithet: terms used to refer to some person, group or other entity but that characterize the entity referred to for rhetorical purposes.

Logical streamlining

When reconstructing arguments we should strive to display the logical relationships in an argument in the simplest, clearest and most familiar ways possible.

  • Where appropriate, rewrite sentences as either conditional or disjunctive sentences of one of the following forms:

    • If A then B
    • If not-A then B
    • A or B
    • Not-A, or B
    • .If not-A then not-B
    • If A then not-B
    • A or not-B
    • Not-A, or not-B
  • Rewrite generalizations in one of the following forms, where the blank ‘_’ is filled by a quantifier such as ‘all’, ‘some’, ‘most’, ‘not’, ‘almost all’, ect
    • _F are G
    • _ are not-G

This is not always possible, and doing it will sometimes distract us from other points we are trying to make.

Implicit and explicit

Not only do actual statements of arguments typically include a lot of material that is inessential to the argument, they often exclude some of what is essential to the argument.

  • Some essential propositions are left implicit.

Our task is to make the argument fully explicit.

A proposition is implicit: the proposition is part of the argument intended by the arguer but it has not actually been stated by the arguer.
To make a proposition explicit: to state it.

Connecting premises

Connecting premise: the premise which you have to make explicit in order to make an argument valid.

Usually, when people give arguments, the premises they give explicitly will be only those which pertain to the particular facts or subject matter they are talking about.
Arguers very often leave implicit the more general assumptions they make.

We cannot assume that whenever an argument, as explicitly given, is neither valid nor inductively forceful, the intended argument is valid or inductively forceful.
It is not always the case that the arguer is implicitly relying on an appropriate connecting premise.

In other cases, the implicit connecting premise is just not true, in which case the argument is unsound.

Covering generalizations

Connecting premises are usually generalisations.

Covering generalisations need not be hard generalisations.
In such a case the inference from generalisation to instance is inductive rather than deductive.

Generalisations of the ‘All A are B’ sort are themselves conditionals, except they are generalised. The same goes for ‘No A are B’ form.

Very often, when people assert conditionals, they do so on the basis of some covering generalisation.

Connecting premises are almost always necessary, but they can fail to be sufficient to bring out the real basis of an argument.

Relevance

When a proposition stated by the arguer is irrelevant to the reasoning that delivers the conclusion, that proposition should not be included in a reconstruction of the argument.

Why not include irrelevant material?

  • It is distracting
  • If the irrelevant material is not true, it can make the argument unsound.

The truth-values of the premises actually advanced by an arguer can be more or less relevant to the soundness of the argument. Sometimes is is highly relevant that a given premise is false, sometimes is its much less so. It depends upon the nature of the mistake, and upon the role played in the argument by the premise.

  • The degree of relevance must be taken into account in the process of reconstruction.

Ambiguity and vagueness

Ambiguity

In reconstructing arguments, we have to eliminate any ambiguities in the original statement of the argument.

  • If the original statement contains an ambiguous sentence, we have to decide which of the possible interpretations was most likely intended by the arguer.
  • In our reconstruction of the argument, we have to rewrite the sentence, choosing a form of words that conveys the intended meaning unambiguously.

A primary purpose of reconstruction is to represent the propositions that constitute an argument in the clearest way.

  • We should have no qualms about changing the language used to express those propositions. In changing it, we are only trying to gain a better grasp of what the arguer was thinking.

There is not guarantee that we will not change or distort the arguer’s thinking, but there is no point in allowing ambiguous language to remain unchanged. We can simply not evaluate an argument if we do not know exactly what argument we are evaluating.

If we cannot decide between two interpretations of an ambiguity, we must give both interpretations of the argument, and evaluate the two arguments independently.

Vagueness

Important for critical reasoning are words whose meanings are vague.
We often have the feeling that these things are bad, or that they are good, without any precise idea of what they mean.
What they signify is typically a whole group or cluster of things that are not unified in any exact way.
(Like liberal or love).

In reconstructing arguments, the best thing to do with vague words is simply to eliminate them.

Many of the most rhetorically highly charged words in public discourse are vague. Eliminating them four our argument-reconstructions achieves two things:

  • it clarifies the argument
  • it enables us to focus without distraction upon the logic of the argument.

The best thing to do with ambiguous or vague language is to replace it with language that is not vague or ambiguous.
The aim is to employ language that will express the intended propositions without ambiguity or vagueness.
But, this is not always possible.

  • In an ambiguous case we can assess each of the possible versions of the argument, but we may have to confess that we cannot tell which version the arguer intended.
  • If the language used is vague, we have to admit that the arguer’s thinking may simply have been vague or confused.

More on generalisations

Soft generalisations are very often expressed without any quantifier at all.

Since there is often confusion over the difference between hard and soft generalisations, we should, when constructing arguments, always make clear whether a generalisation is hard or soft. (The one exception to this is the case of statements about cause and effect).

  • If an intended quantifier is merely implicit, there is room for misinterpretation. It is a kind of ambiguity.

The way to eliminate the ambiguity is to add an explicit quantifier.

The scope of generalisation

Subjects of generalisations: what the generalisations are about.

The scope of generalisations: how big the subject is.
It can be wider and narrower.

(For example: all cows or all black cows).

We can compare generalisation scopes only when the subject of one is a subset of the subject of the other.

It can sometimes be important to adjust the scope of a generalisation, making it either narrower or wider.
Usually, in reconstructing arguments, we have to narrow them.

By narrowing the generalisation, the issue is defined more exactly.

When reconstructing arguments, we should take care not to employ a hard generalisation that is wider in scope than we need if there is anything doubtful about the wider one that could be eliminated by employing a narrower one.
If a narrower (but hard) generalisation will suffice for constructing an argument for the desired conclusion, when we should employ the narrower one.

This is not to say we should always choose narrow generalisations whenever possible!

In some cases there is not natural word or phrase for the class of cases we wish to generalise about. In such cases we have to reduce the scope of a generalisation by explicitly accepting a certain class of what would otherwise be counterexamples.

Practical reasoning

Practical conclusions: a conclusion that enjoins or commends a particular action.
What the argument says is that doing one thing in necessary if a certain desirable outcome or end is to be achieved.

Practical reasoning: means-end reasoning.
Based upon two sorts of considerations:

  • an outcome is specified as being either desirable or undesirable.
  • There is a proposition put forwards that says either:
    • if such-and-such action is performed, the outcome will result
    • if the action is performed, the outcome will not result
    • .if the action is not performed the outcome will not come about
    • if the action is not performed the outcome will not come about

But:

  • We need to know that the cost of the proposed action does not outweigh the benefit of the outcome.
  • We need to know that there is not some other means that would bring about the same benefit but at lower costs. We need to know that the proposed action is the most efficient or economical way to bring about the desired outcome.

In reconstructing arguments, we need to incorporate both of the points above as premises.

Balancing costs, benefits and probabilities

Practical reasoning involves a weighing of one value (the value of the desired result) against another value (the negative value of the cost of the envisaged means of bringing about the desired result).
Almost any action could, in principle, be rationalised by practical reason.

In cases when the argument must be represented as inductive, we have to juggle three factors

  • Cost
  • Benefit
  • Probability.

There are only rough estimates. No one assumes that anyone can specify exactly how bad or how good outcomes would be relative to each other.

Expected value: for each possible outcome of the action, you multiply the probability of the outcome by its value (its cost or benefit, as the case may be). Then you add these figures together.

When given a range of possible actions, one should do whatever maximises expected value.

There is a certain limit to the application of expected value calculations: the expected value of a proposed action tells us whether or not it would be rational to do something, unless it is overridden by the existence of rights or moral rules.

Explanations as conclusions

In an explanation, the truth-value of that proposition is not in question.

Use the word ‘cause’ or ‘because’ in the conclusion.

Abduction

The generalisations appealed to in arguments of this kind are often soft rather than hard, and more generally the arguments can be inductive rather than deductive.

Abductive argument: an inductive explanation.
The best and most likely explanation.

Causal generalisations

Causal statements often appear as generalisations about types of events or states of affairs.

The word ‘cause’ does not always, or even typically, indicate hard generalisation of this kind.

In order to infer a causal relationship from a correlation between X and Y, we need to know that the correlation holds, or would hold, even when other possible causes of Y are absent or were present.

A short cut

Where an argument contains a conditional among its premises, we have, in order to infer the consequent of the conditional, to write down its antecedent as a separate premise.

If P2 is a conditional whose antecedent is P1, instead of rewriting P1 out in full, we may abbreviate its simply as ‘P1’.

 

Access: 
Public

Image

This content is also used in .....

Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition) - a summary

Introducing Arguments - summary of chapter 1 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Introducing Arguments - summary of chapter 1 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Image

Critical thinking
Chapter 1
Introducing Arguments

To attempt to persuade by giving good reasons is to give an argument.


Beginning to think critically: recognizing arguments

Not all attempts to persuade (using language) are attempts to persuade by argument.

  • some are attempts to persuade by means of rhetorical devices

Rhetoric: any verbal or written attempt to persuade someone to believe, desire or do something that does not attempt to give good reasons for the belief, desire or action, but attempts to motivate that belief, desire or action solely through the power of the words used.

An attempt to persuade by argument is an attempt to provide you with reasons for believing a claim, desiring something or doing something.
Arguments appeal to your critical faculties, your reason.

Rhetoric tends to rely on the persuasive power of certain words and verbal techniques to influence your beliefs, desires and actions by appeal to your desires, fears and other feelings.

  • threats and bribes are arguments (not rhetorics), for they give a reason to do something

Rhetorical techniques can be manipulative and coercive. Their use should generally be avoided by those who aspire to think critically and to persuade by reason.
When analysing attempts to persuade, we have to perform three tasks:

  • Identify the issue being discussed, and determine whether or not the writer or speaker is attempting to persuade by means of argument. Is an argument being presented?
  • Reconstructing the argument so as to express it clearly, and so as to demonstrate clearly the steps and form of the argument’s reasoning
  • Evaluating the argument, asking what’s good about it and what’s bad about it.

When we put forward an argument we are either advancing an opinion or recommending an action.
In either case we give a number of claims intended to support the claim or the recommendation.

These two types of argument can be collapsed into one.

All arguments can be understood as attempting to provide reasons for thinking that some claim is true (it states how things really are).
To say that a claim is true is to say that what is claimed is how things actually are.

A

.....read more
Access: 
Public
Language and rhetoric - summary of chapter 2 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Language and rhetoric - summary of chapter 2 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Image

Critical thinking
Chapter 2

Language and rhetoric


Linguistic phenomena

Once we’ve determined that a text or a speech contains an attempt to persuade by argument, the remainder of argument-reconstruction is largely a matter of interpreting the speech or text as accurately as possible.

Ambiguity

Ambiguity can be used, often deliberately, to obfuscate the content of an argument or rhetorically to obscure the persuaders true point.
A sentence is ambiguous in a given context when there is more than one possible way of interpreting it in that context.

There are two types of ambiguity:

  • Lexical ambiguity
  • Syntactic ambiguity

Lexical ambiguity

Lexical ambiguity: a property of individual words and phrases that occurs when the word or phrase has more than one meaning.

Extension: the set or group of things to which an expression applies.
(for example, the extension of the word ‘cow’ are all the cows in the world).

An ambiguous word or phrase has two or more separate and different extensions.
Ambiguous words and phrases can bring their ambiguity into sentences, making those sentences capable of having more than one possible interpretation.

Words that are potentially lexically ambiguous are not necessarily ambiguous in every context.

When interpreting sentences that are lexically ambiguous, we have to focus on the context in which they are written or said and the consequent probability of each of the possible interpretations being the correct one.

Syntactic ambiguity

Syntactic ambiguity: when the arrangement of words in a sentence is such that the sentence could be understood in more than one way.

Vagueness
 

The meaning of a word or expression is vague if it is indefinite or if it is uncertain what is conveyed by the word in the context under consideration.

Sometimes, someone aware of the weakness of their own position will deliberately leave their meaning vague in order to camouflage that weakness and to evoke strong feelings of approval or disapproval in their readers or listeners.

Words can also have a clear meaning, but which have an indefinitely demarcated extension.
(like colors)

Primary and secondary connotation

The rich secondary connotation (bijbetekenis) of some words provides a further source of vagueness.

Primary connotation: a given thing falls within a word’s extension if,

.....read more
Access: 
Public
Logic: deductive validity - summary of chapter 3 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Logic: deductive validity - summary of chapter 3 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Image

Wst-r
Chapter 3

Logic: deductive validity

Argument reconstruction: the representation of arguments in standard form, so as to give us a clear and comprehensive view of them.

Argument assessment: the determination of whether or not arguments provide good reasons for accepting their conclusions.


The principle of charity

An argument is a system of propositions.
Propositions: a set of premises advanced in support of a conclusion.

People succeed in expressing the propositions they have in mind in varying degrees of clarity. An argument may depend upon premises that the arguer does not state at all, but which he or she is implicitly assuming.

Since the purpose of argument-reconstruction is to determine exactly what argument has been given, part of the task is to clarify what the arguer actually said, and to supplement what the arguer actually said (to make explicit what was merely implicit in the arguer’s statements).

  • The sentences we use in a reconstruction of the argument need not to be the very same sentences as used by the arguer in giving their argument. We may employ sentences that more clearly or precisely express the propositions that constitute the argument.
  • Our reconstructed version of the argument may contain premises that are not expressed by any of the sentences actually used by the arguer.

Argument-reconstruction is essentially a task of interpretation.

The principle of charity.

In such facts pertaining to the context in which the argument is given, together with the specific words used by the person, will constitute the total evidence you have for reconstructing the argument.

  • In some cases, the context is known, and makes it obvious what the arguer was implicitly assuming.
  • In other cases, we may have to learn more about the context.
  • In some other cases, however, we may learn all the relevant contextual factors, yet it remains possible to represent the person’s argument in more than one way.

If, in the third case, you have to chose what representation of the argument is true, it depends on your purpose.

  • If you are hoping to convince others that the person is wrong, you are most likely to succeed if you represent it as a bad one.
  • If what
.....read more
Access: 
Public
The practice of argument-reconstruction - summary of chapter 5 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

The practice of argument-reconstruction - summary of chapter 5 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Image

Critical thinking
Chapter 5

The practice of argument-reconstruction


Extraneous material

The first step in reconstructing an argument is to make a list of the argument’s premises and conclusion as concisely and clearly as possible.
Making such a list is only the first step towards a complete reconstruction.

Defusing the rhetoric

Expressive epithet: terms used to refer to some person, group or other entity but that characterize the entity referred to for rhetorical purposes.

Logical streamlining

When reconstructing arguments we should strive to display the logical relationships in an argument in the simplest, clearest and most familiar ways possible.

  • Where appropriate, rewrite sentences as either conditional or disjunctive sentences of one of the following forms:
    • If A then B
    • If not-A then B
    • A or B
    • Not-A, or B
    • .If not-A then not-B
    • If A then not-B
    • A or not-B
    • Not-A, or not-B
  • Rewrite generalizations in one of the following forms, where the blank ‘_’ is filled by a quantifier such as ‘all’, ‘some’, ‘most’, ‘not’, ‘almost all’, ect
    • _F are G
    • _ are not-G

This is not always possible, and doing it will sometimes distract us from other points we are trying to make.

Implicit and explicit

Not only do actual statements of arguments typically include a lot of material that is inessential to the argument, they often exclude some of what is essential to the argument.

  • Some essential propositions are left implicit.

Our task is to make the argument fully explicit.

A proposition is implicit: the proposition is part of the argument intended by the arguer but it has not actually been stated by the arguer.
To make a proposition explicit: to state it.

.....read more
Access: 
Public
Issues in argument assessment - summary of chapter 6 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Issues in argument assessment - summary of chapter 6 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Image

Critical thinking
Chapter 6
Issues in argument assessment


Rational persuasiveness

The role of an argument is to give us reasons for accepting its conclusion as true.
The aim is to give an argument by which the intended audience is ought to be persuaded.

We cannot always tell whether or not the argument is sound.
Sound arguments must have true premises.

  • An deductively sound argument is one that has true premises and which is deductively valid.
  • An inductively sound argument is one with true premises that is inductively forceful.

Since we do not always know which propositions are true and which false, we cannot always tell whether an argument is sound or not.

To say that an inductively forceful argument is defeated for a person: the person reasonably believes the premises, but, nevertheless, reasonably rejects the conclusion.
(They have, for example, extra information).

An inductively forceful argument whose premises you have reason to accept is rationally persuasive only if your total evidence does not defeat the argument for you.

To say that an argument is rationally persuasive for a person:

  • the argument is either deductively or inductively forceful
  • the person reasonably believes the argument’s premises (at the time)
  • it is not an inductively forceful argument that is defeated for that person (at that time).

Rationally unpersuasive argument: an argument that is deductively sound and valid, but gets you no closer to knowing the truth-value of the conclusion.

Rational persuasiveness is doubly relative.

  • An argument is or is not rationally persuasive for a person at a particular time.

Since people are in different states of information at different times, an argument may be rationally persuasive for one person, but not for another.

Seven points to bear in mind as regards rational persuasiveness:

1 It  is not possible for the conclusion of a deductively valid argument to be defeated by a person’s total evidence. This is only possible for inductively forceful arguments.

  • If you accept with good reason the premises of an argument that you recognize to be deductively valid, you must accept the conclusion as well.
  • The adverb ‘probably’ (or a similar term) before the conclusion of an inductively forceful argument allows the possibility that the premises are true and the conclusion is false.

2 Rational persuasiveness is not part of the definition that the argument be sound (either deductively or inductively).

  • The notion of rational persuasiveness is intended to capture what it is about an argument that constitutes its rational claim on a person.
    (For example: an argument can have a false premise,
.....read more
Access: 
Public
Pseudo-reasoning - summary of chapter 7 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Pseudo-reasoning - summary of chapter 7 of Critical thinking: A concise guide by Bowell & Kemp (4th edition)

Image

Critical thinking
Chapter 7
Pseudo-reasoning


Fallacies

Fallacies count as arguments in the sense that they fit our definition of an argument. They consist of a set of propositions, some of which premises, one of which is a conclusion. But, one way or another, they are bad arguments.
A fallacy: a mistake in reasoning.

One commits a fallacy when the reasons advanced or accepted in support of a claim fail to justify its acceptance.
A fallacy can be committed either when one is deciding whether to accept a claim on the basis of a fallacious argument with which one has been presented or when one is presented the fallacious argument oneself.

A fallacious argument or inference: one in which there is an inappropriate connection between premises and conclusion.
Almost all fallacies fall under one of the following two types:

  • Formal fallacies: the inappropriate connections are failures of logical connection. The argument of inference is neither deductively valid nor inductively forceful, even where all implicit premises have been made explicit.
  • Substantive (or informal) fallacies: the inappropriate connections involve reliance on some very general unjustified assumptions or inferences. We need only make these premises explicit in order to see that they are false and unjustified. The implicit, false or dubious premise will be of a general nature, having nothing specifically to do with the subject matter of the argument.

The majority of fallacies that we encounter in everyday texts and speech are substantive fallacies.

A fallacious argument can have true or false premises.
Simply having false premises does not make an argument fallacious.
Nor does having true premises guarantee that an argument is not fallacious.

A proposition accepted on the basis of a fallacious argument may turn out to be true as a matter of actual fact.

The best way to become acquainted with the different types of fallacies is to practise identifying and analysing them.
As they are attempts to persuade by argument, you need to reconstruct them in standard form and then use techniques of argument analyses and assessment to demonstrate the ways in which they are fallacious.

Many types of fallacious argument are effective as rhetorical ploys.

Formal fallacies

Formal fallacies: patterns of argument whose reasoning makes purely logical mistakes.
Each type of fallacy constitutes an invalid argument.
The fallacies will be recognized by the presence of the particular invalid pattern.

Affirming the consequent of a conditional

Affirming the consequent for short.
This occurs when we argue from the conditional premise that if P (the antecedent), then Q (the consequent) together with the premise that Q to the conclusion that P.

P1) If P then Q
P2) Q
---------------------

.....read more
Access: 
Public
Everything you need for the course WSRt of the second year of Psychology at the Uva

Everything you need for the course WSRt of the second year of Psychology at the Uva

Image

This magazine contains all the summaries you need for the course WSRt at the second year of psychology at the Uva.

Access: 
Public
Follow the author: SanneA
More contributions of WorldSupporter author: SanneA:
Comments, Compliments & Kudos:

Add new contribution

CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Image CAPTCHA
Enter the characters shown in the image.
Promotions
Image
The JoHo Insurances Foundation is specialized in insurances for travel, work, study, volunteer, internships an long stay abroad
Check the options on joho.org (international insurances) or go direct to JoHo's https://www.expatinsurances.org

 

Check how to use summaries on WorldSupporter.org


Online access to all summaries, study notes en practice exams

Using and finding summaries, study notes en practice exams on JoHo WorldSupporter

There are several ways to navigate the large amount of summaries, study notes en practice exams on JoHo WorldSupporter.

  1. Starting Pages: for some fields of study and some university curricula editors have created (start) magazines where customised selections of summaries are put together to smoothen navigation. When you have found a magazine of your likings, add that page to your favorites so you can easily go to that starting point directly from your profile during future visits. Below you will find some start magazines per field of study
  2. Use the menu above every page to go to one of the main starting pages
  3. Tags & Taxonomy: gives you insight in the amount of summaries that are tagged by authors on specific subjects. This type of navigation can help find summaries that you could have missed when just using the search tools. Tags are organised per field of study and per study institution. Note: not all content is tagged thoroughly, so when this approach doesn't give the results you were looking for, please check the search tool as back up
  4. Follow authors or (study) organizations: by following individual users, authors and your study organizations you are likely to discover more relevant study materials.
  5. Search tool : 'quick & dirty'- not very elegant but the fastest way to find a specific summary of a book or study assistance with a specific course or subject. The search tool is also available at the bottom of most pages

Do you want to share your summaries with JoHo WorldSupporter and its visitors?

Quicklinks to fields of study (main tags and taxonomy terms)

Field of study

Check related topics:
Activities abroad, studies and working fields
Countries and regions
Institutions and organizations
WorldSupporter and development goals
Access level of this page
  • Public
  • WorldSupporters only
  • JoHo members
  • Private
Statistics
6301