Critical thinking - English summary 12th edition
- 1580 keer gelezen
There are two techniques for creating and evaluating deductive arguments. This chapter is mainly about categorical logic. This is logic based on the relationships of inclusion and exclusion between categories in categorical claims. Categorical logic is useful in clarifying and analysing deductive arguments. When we understand how this works, we can be more critical and precise with regard to propositions and arguments and avoid ambiguity.
A categorical claim says something about categories of objects. A standard-form categorical claim is a claim that arises when names or descriptions are added to categories. Here are four types of:
By "some" we mean "at least one."
The words that appear on the dotted lines above are called terms. The word that appears on the first dotted line in a claim is called the "subject term". The word that appears on the second dot line is called the "predicate term."
The words that serve as "subject term" and "predicate term" in a sentence are collectively also called classes. The above claims can also be processed and displayed in Venn diagrams. Such a Venn diagram is a graphical representation of all possible hypothetical logical relationships between a finite set of statements. Visually, this is a circle for each category, overlapping the moment they have a community. Thanks to the overlap between some statements, you can draw conclusions from the statements; proportions are visible.
The claim "some dogs bite" would therefore be represented by two overlapping circles - one circle for "dogs" and one circle for "bite". The overlap is therefore "dogs that bite". Because this claim concerns all dogs, but for some dogs you put a cross in the overlapping piece to indicate that at least one dog is biting.
The A and I claims are called affirmative claims because they include part of another class. The E and O claims are called negative claims because they exclude a part of one class from another.
It is important to be able to convert a claim into a standard-form categorical claim that means the same. We say that two claims are the same ("equivalent claims") when they are both the same in exactly every situation. This conversion must be done precisely so that the meaning of the claim is not changed. For some claims that is easy. The claim "Every rose is a flower" can easily be transformed into an A claim, namely: "All roses are flowers." However, sometimes it is more difficult to transform a claim into one of the four standard-form categorical claims. It is therefore important, when having a discussion or debate or paper, to first determine the terms that appear in a claim.
We say that two categorical claims correspond when they have the same subject term and the same predicate term. So the claim "All Protestants are Christians" corresponds to "Some Protestants are Christians." In both claims, "Protestants" is the subject term, while "Christians" is the predicate term. The claim "Some Christians are not Protestant" does not correspond to the above two claims, because the places of the subject term and the predicate term are interchanged in this claim. Logical relationships between A, E, I, and O claims can be explained in a figure: the square of opposition ("square of opposition" see page 263).
With the help of the square of opposition we can often read the truth values of the claims. There are a number of limitations to this:
Converting a standard-form categorical claim can be done by reversing the position of the subject term and the predicate term. Only the E and I claims contain the same information as their conversions. Therefore, the conclusion is: Only E and I claims, but not the A and O claims, are equal to their conversations. Schematically; P = Q, Q = P
Examples are:
In addition to conversion, obversion is a second categorical implementation. Before this concept is explained, two other concepts must first be understood:
Finding the reverse ('obverse') of a claim can be done in two ways: (1) turn an affirmative claim into a negative claim or vice versa, so make an A claim an E claim or turn an O claim an I claim and (2) replace the predicate term with the complementary term.
Schematically; ~ P = Q, P = ~ Q
Example:
All categorical claims, whether they belong in the A, E, I or O category, are the same as their opposite form.
A third categorical implementation is called contraposition. To find the contraposition of a categorical claim, (1) the subject term must be placed in the place of the predicate term, while the predicate term is placed in the place of the subject term. In addition (2) both terms must be replaced by complementary terms. Schematically; P = Q, ~ P = ~ Q
Example;
Only A and O claims are the same as their counter position.
A monergism is a deductive argument that consists of two premises. A categorical syllogism is a syllogism that consists of standard-form categorical claims, where three terms of each claim must occur exactly twice in two of the claims.
An example:
All terms ("Americans", "consumers" and "Democrats") appear exactly twice in two different claims.
The terms of a syllogism get the following label:
When S and P are connected by means of M, then an argument is valid. An argument is called valid if it is not possible for the premises to be true, while the conclusion is false. A Venn diagram can be used to find out the relationship between S, P and M, so that it can be seen whether an argument is valid (for explanation and examples, see "The Venn diagram method of testing for validity" on pages 274 and 275).
A Venn diagram consists of three circles: on the left is the minor term, on the right is the major term and below that is the middle term. When one of the premises is an I or O premise, there may be confusion about where the "X" should be placed. A decision can sometimes be made using the following rules:
Categorical syllogisms can also be hidden in unspoken premises. It is then important to name the unspoken premises and to write out the categorical syllogisms step by step.
In addition to drawing up a Venn diagram, there is an easier method to test the validity. This method is based on three simple rules (see below). These rules are based on two concepts: (1) affirmative and negative categorical claims and (2) the concept of distribution. Distribution occurs when a claim says something about each member of a category. There is no distribution if a claim does not say something about every member of a category.
A syllogism is valid if the following three rules are met:
Example: (1) "All students are people," (2) "Some people are not employees." Conclusion: (3) "Some students are not employees". The term "people" is the M and is not distributed in both premises. The first premise is an A-claim and is not distributed in terms of predicate term and the second premise (an O-claim) is not distributed in terms of subject term. This syllogism therefore does not meet the criteria of rule two. This means that this argument is not valid.
Syllogisms are important for science because with syllogisms you can draw a conclusion that is true from two arguments that are true. So you can check whether an argument is valid. An example:
Join with a free account for more service, or become a member for full access to exclusives and extra support of WorldSupporter >>
There are several ways to navigate the large amount of summaries, study notes en practice exams on JoHo WorldSupporter.
Do you want to share your summaries with JoHo WorldSupporter and its visitors?
Main summaries home pages:
Main study fields:
Business organization and economics, Communication & Marketing, Education & Pedagogic Sciences, International Relations and Politics, IT and Technology, Law & Administration, Medicine & Health Care, Nature & Environmental Sciences, Psychology and behavioral sciences, Science and academic Research, Society & Culture, Tourisme & Sports
Main study fields NL:
JoHo can really use your help! Check out the various student jobs here that match your studies, improve your competencies, strengthen your CV and contribute to a more tolerant world
1727 |
Add new contribution